+ All documents
Home > Documents > Does the motor system contribute to the perception and understanding of actions? Reflections on...

Does the motor system contribute to the perception and understanding of actions? Reflections on...

Date post: 19-Nov-2023
Category:
Upload: independent
View: 1 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
27
Language and Cognition http://journals.cambridge.org/LCO Additional services for Language and Cognition: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Does the motor system contribute to the perception and understanding of actions? Reections on Gregory Hickok’s The myth of mirror neurons: the real neuroscience of communication and cognition DAVID KEMMERER Language and Cognition / FirstView Article / December 2014, pp 1 26 DOI: 10.1017/langcog.2014.36, Published online: 02 December 2014 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1866980814000362 How to cite this article: DAVID KEMMERER Does the motor system contribute to the perception and understanding of actions? Reections on Gregory Hickok’s The myth of mirror neurons: the real neuroscience of communication and cognition. Language and Cognition, Available on CJO 2014 doi:10.1017/langcog.2014.36 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/LCO, IP address: 128.210.206.145 on 03 Dec 2014
Transcript

Language  and  Cognitionhttp://journals.cambridge.org/LCO

Additional  services  for  Language  and  Cognition:

Email  alerts:  Click  hereSubscriptions:  Click  hereCommercial  reprints:  Click  hereTerms  of  use  :  Click  here

Does  the  motor  system  contribute  to  theperception  and  understanding  of  actions?Reflections  on  Gregory  Hickok’s  The  myth  ofmirror  neurons:  the  real  neuroscience  ofcommunication  and  cognition

DAVID  KEMMERER

Language  and  Cognition  /  FirstView  Article  /  December  2014,  pp  1  -­  26DOI:  10.1017/langcog.2014.36,  Published  online:  02  December  2014

Link  to  this  article:  http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1866980814000362

How  to  cite  this  article:DAVID  KEMMERER  Does  the  motor  system  contribute  to  the  perception  andunderstanding  of  actions?  Reflections  on  Gregory  Hickok’s  The  myth  of  mirrorneurons:  the  real  neuroscience  of  communication  and  cognition.  Language  andCognition,  Available  on  CJO  2014  doi:10.1017/langcog.2014.36

Request  Permissions  :  Click  here

Downloaded  from  http://journals.cambridge.org/LCO,  IP  address:  128.210.206.145  on  03  Dec  2014

1

Language and Cognition (2014), Page 1 of 26 . doi:10.1017/langcog.2014.36© UK Cognitive Linguistics Association, 2014

Does the motor system contribute to the perception and understanding of actions? Refl ections on Gregory

Hickok’s The myth of mirror neurons: the real neuroscience of communication and cognition *

DAVID KEMMERER

Department of Speech , Language , and Hearing Sciences , Department of Psychological Sciences , Purdue University

( Received 26 September 2014 – Revised 30 September 2014 – Accepted 03 October 2014 )

abstract It has been said that mirror neurons are “the most hyped concept in neuroscience” (Jarrett, 2012 ). In his book The myth of mirror neurons: the real neuroscience of communication and cognition (2014), Gregory Hickok does the fi eld a great service by cutting through this hype and showing that, contrary to the views of many laypeople as well as some experts, mirror neurons are not the fundamental ‘basis’ of action understanding. I argue here, however, that he takes his critique too far by eff ectively denying that the motor system plays any signifi cant role at all in the perception and interpretation of actions. In fact, a large literature strongly supports the hypothesis that motor regions in the frontal and parietal lobes not only subserve the execution of actions, but also contribute to the comprehension of actions, regardless of whether they are directly observed or linguistically represented. In addition, recent research suggests that although the articulatory system is involved primarily in speech production, it enhances speech perception too, even when the auditory stimuli are not explicitly attended.

1 . Introduction Given that the overarching aim of modern neuroscience is to elucidate the biological bases of our very own minds, it is hardly surprising that in recent years many of the fi eld’s most important advances have been presented to the general public through popular newspapers, magazines, television shows, and websites. This growing media attention has certainly increased people’s

[ * ] Address for correspondence: David Kemmerer, Department of Speech, Language, and Hearing Sciences, Lyles-Porter Hall, Purdue University, 715 Clinic Drive, West Lafayette, IN 47907. tel: (765) 494-3826; e-mail: [email protected]

david kemmerer

2

awareness and appreciation of brain research, but it has also led to an unwarranted glorifi cation of all things ‘neuro’. One reason for this extreme reaction is that when the key fi ndings get fi ltered through the prismatic perspectives of journalists, pundits, and other non-experts, their nature often becomes oversimplifi ed and their signifi cance exaggerated. Another reason, though, is that even experts are not always successful at resisting the temptation to overinterpret exciting new discoveries, especially when those discoveries appear to have profound implications, as they sometimes do. Due to both of these factors, a strong backlash is now underway, as exemplifi ed by books such as Paolo Legrenzi and Carlo Umiltà’s Neuromania: on the limits of brain science (2011), Sally Satel and Scott Lilienfeld’s Brainwashed: on the seductive appeal of mindless neuroscience (2013), and Raymond Tallis’s Aping mankind: neuromania, Darwinitis, and the misrepresentation of humanity (2014).

One of the latest installments in this genre, Gregory Hickok’s The myth of mirror neurons: the real neuroscience of communication and cognition (2014), is particularly noteworthy because it focuses on what has been called “the most hyped concept in neuroscience” (Jarrett, 2012 ). Mirror neurons were fi rst discovered in 1992 by Giacomo Rizzolatti and his colleagues in Parma, Italy (di Pellegrino, Fadiga, Fogassi, Gallese, & Rizzolatti, 1992; for reviews see Kilner & Lemon, 2013 ; Rizzolatti, Catttaneo, Fabbri-Destro, & Rozzi, 2014 ). Basically, the distinguishing property of these cells is that they discharge not only when an individual performs a specifi c type of action (e.g., a thumb–forefi nger precision grip), but also when that individual sees someone else perform an identical or similar type of action. To be sure, such fi ring patterns are quite intriguing, since they suggest that action observation is closely related to action execution. During the past few decades, however, mirror neurons have attracted so much attention from both scientists and laypeople that they have been claimed to play critical roles in an ever-expanding array of psychological phenomena, ranging from more or less plausible domains like action understanding, language, and mind-reading, to increasingly far-fetched ones like political attitudes, mass hysteria, and sexual orientation.

Hickok’s primary aim is to expose what he believes to be a number of fundamental problems with mirror neuron theorizing. He doesn’t waste much time with the obviously eccentric interpretations, but instead devotes most of his book to attacking the core hypothesis – associated most prominently with Rizzolatti’s team – that mirror neurons allow people to comprehend each other’s behavior at a deep level by unconsciously simulating the observed movements in their own motor systems. As he indicates in the Preface, during the late 2000s, when everyone seemed to be jumping on the mirror neuron bandwagon, he took it upon himself to become more familiar with the relevant literature and ended up thinking that the conclusions simply weren’t supported by the data. He expressed this opinion as follows in his blog,

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

3

Talking Brains : “We all agree that mirror neurons are very interesting neural creatures, but the idea that they are the basis for action understanding is darn near incoherent.” Then he wrote a critique called “Eight problems for the mirror neuron theory of action understanding in monkeys and humans”, and it not only became the most downloaded paper from the Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, but served as the springboard for the book.

My goal here is not to review Hickok’s whole book, but rather to evaluate his major criticisms of the action understanding account of mirror neurons. I fi rst discuss how these issues pertain to the observation of other people’s behavior, and then I consider how they bear on two aspects of language processing – namely, comprehending linguistically represented actions, and perceiving speech. Before delving into the details, however, a few preliminary remarks are in order about my general strategy.

At a critical juncture in Chapter 7 (pp. 180–181), Hickok makes the following point: “‘Understanding’ is a complicated thing with lots of moving parts. You can’t pull out one part and call that the ‘basis of action understanding.’ It doesn’t work for just the motor bits and it doesn’t work for just the sensory bits.” I completely agree (Kemmerer, Gonzalez-Castillo, Talavage, Patterson, & Wiley, 2008 ; Kemmerer, Rudrauf, Manzel, & Tranel, 2012 ), and so do many other researchers (e.g., Barsalou, 2013 ; Damasio & Meyer, 2008 ; Spunt & Lieberman, 2012 ; Van Overwalle & Baetens, 2009 ). But Hickok goes on to make another claim: “The motor part, while associated with the action for sure, is such a minute part of the bigger picture as to be virtually useless on its own. At the very most, one could possibly argue that accessing a motor copy of the perceived action could help facilitate or speed access to the broader, nonmotor network that enables understanding.” Similar attempts to minimize the functional contribution of the mirror system to action understanding appear in several other chapters, too, but my sense is that most of these eff orts are misguided. In fact, my main concern about Hickok’s book is that in his zeal to undermine the overly strong view that mirror neurons are the sole ‘basis’ of action understanding, he veers too far in the opposite direction, denying that they play any signifi cant role at all in that process. As I demonstrate below, although many problems remain unresolved, a substantial amount of evidence does support the notion that the motor cortices of the human brain make non-trivial contributions to both the perception and the interpretation of other people’s actions, not only when those actions are directly observed, but also when they are conveyed by speech.

2 . Observing other people’s actions At the beginning of Chapter 3, Hickok acknowledges that “it is a virtual given that humans have mirror neurons” (p. 27). But then he spends the rest of the

david kemmerer

4

chapter painting a mostly negative picture of the work that has been done during the past twenty years to delineate the mirror system in the human brain. For instance, he cites Grèzes and Decety’s ( 2001 ) meta-analysis of the fi rst wave of functional neuroimaging studies (i.e., studies employing either positron emission tomography [PET] or functional magnetic resonance imaging [fMRI]) to justify the statement that “if you looked across many studies you could fi nd evidence for Broca’s area activating during observation in one study and during execution in another, but if you were to plot the precise location of these studies, as a 2001 study did, very little direct overlap was evident in the human homologue of monkey area F5, the core of the mirror system” (pp. 36–37, emphasis in original). However, neither here nor in any other part of the book does Hickok mention that as the fi eld continued to evolve, further meta-analyses were conducted that not only included a larger number of experiments but also employed more sophisticated methods, and all of them did reveal that both action execution and action observation tend to engage the posterior part of Broca’s area as well several other regions, most notably the premotor cortex and anterior intraparietal sulcus (see Figure 1 ; Van Overwalle & Baetens, 2009 ; Molenberghs, Cunnington, & Mattingley, 2012 ; see also Caspers, Zilles, Laird, & Eikhoff , 2010 ).

In Chapters 4 and 8, Hickok advocates the view that mirror neurons do not signifi cantly enhance action understanding per se, but instead play a role in action selection by virtue of participating in sensory-motor mappings (see also Cook, Bird, Catmur, Press, & Heyes, 2014 ). To support this purely associative position, he summarizes a study by Catmur, Walsh, and Heyes ( 2007 ) that used transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) to show that it is possible to create ‘counter mirror neurons’. The investigators fi rst demonstrated that, in keeping with previous research, when the subjects watched someone else move either an index fi nger or a pinky fi nger, the motor excitability of their own corresponding fi nger increased. Then they trained the subjects to respond to the sight of an index fi nger movement by making a pinky fi nger movement, and to respond to the sight of a pinky fi nger movement by making an index fi nger movement. Afterward, they found that when the subjects saw an index fi nger movement, the motor excitability of their own pinky fi nger increased, and when they saw a pinky fi nger movement, the motor excitability of their own index fi nger increased. Hickok argues that these results challenge the mirror neuron theory of action understanding because “if you can alter the motor response without aff ecting perception, then the motor response can’t be the basis of the percept” (p. 54). This is not really a valid conclusion, however, because other studies have shown that learning arbitrary visuomotor rules does not eliminate normal mirror responses; on the contrary, normal mirror responses still occur in an early time window (150–250 ms post stimulus onset), whereas trained ‘counter mirror’ responses do not occur until a late

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

5

Fig. 1. Activation peaks from fMRI studies of the mirror system, plotted according to Talairach y-z coordinates. The posterior superior temporal sulcus (pSTS) is engaged during the visual perception of whole-body motion (green circles) and gaze direction (yellow circles), whereas the premotor cortex (PMC) and anterior intraparietal sulcus (aIPS) – which constitute what are traditionally regarded as the two main components of the mirror system – are recruited during the execution of hand actions (dark blue circles), the imitation of hand actions (light blue circles), the observation of hand actions and, in a few studies, mouth or foot actions (green diamonds), and the understanding of the immediate goals of perceived actions (orange squares). A = left hemisphere; B = right hemisphere; horizontal y axis = anterior–posterior dimension; vertical z axis = superior–inferior dimension (from Van Overwalle & Baetens, 2009 , p. 576; reproduced with permission).

david kemmerer

6

time window (300–320 ms post stimulus onset) (Barchiesi & Cattaneo, 2013 ; Ubaldi, Barchiesi, & Cattaneo, in press ). These fi ndings therefore leave open the possibility that the mirror system does contribute to the perception and interpretation of actions, and that possibility has received increasing support from numerous TMS studies ( Figure 2 ) and lesion studies ( Figure 3 ).

Starting with perception, in Chapter 7 Hickok correctly notes that the observation of biological motion patterns recruits the posterior superior temporal sulcus (pSTS; Figure 1 ), but he neglects to mention that it also depends on the inferior frontal cortex (IFC, including specifi cally the posterior part of Broca’s area and the ventral premotor cortex). Evidence comes from research showing that when subjects are asked to detect point-light walkers amid noisy backgrounds, not only does their performance improve as the amount of gray matter increases in both the pSTS and the IFC (Gilaie-Dotan, Kanai, Bahrami, Rees, & Saygin, 2013 ), but their performance is also disrupted by TMS (van Kemenade, Muggleton, Walsh, & Saygin, 2012 ) or structural damage (Saygin, 2007 ) to either region. In addition, the ability to discriminate between pictures of slightly diff erent actions is impaired by TMS (Urgesi, Calvo-Merino, Haggard, & Aglioti, 2007a ; Urgesi, Candidi, Ionta, & Aglioti, 2007b ; Jacquet & Avenanti, in press ) or structural damage (Moro, Urgesi, Pernigo, Lanteri, Pazzaglia, & Aglioti, 2008 ) to the IFC. And when subjects watch an actor lift boxes of diff erent weights, TMS to the IFC interferes with their capacity to estimate the weights of the boxes (Pobric & Hamilton, 2006 ) and to judge whether the actor is trying to deceive them about those weights (Tidoni, Borgomaneri, di Pellegrino, & Avenanti, 2013 ). Yet another remarkable discovery is that a brain-damaged patient whose lesion aff ected the left inferior, middle, and superior frontal gyri violated Fitts’s law (Fitts, 1954 ) during both the execution and the observation of actions (Eskenazi, Grosjean, Humphreys, & Knoblich, 2009 ). This law is perhaps the most well-established principle of motor control, and it basically captures speed–accuracy trade-off s, stating that “the average time it takes to move between two targets is determined by the width of the targets and the distance separating them” (Eskenazi et al., 2009 , p. 479). Hickok does not discuss any of these fi ndings, but all of them (among others) bolster the idea that the IFC, which is a major component of the mirror system, plays a genuinely causal role in the perception of actions. It may use unconscious motor simulations in a predictive manner to constrain the perceptual processing of observed actions, or it may use them to construct more complete action representations from partial, subtle, or ambiguous visual cues (Kilner, Friston, & Frith, 2007 ; Urgesi, Candidi, & Avenanti, 2014 ; Wilson & Knoblich, 2005 ). In this connection, it is also noteworthy that more superior sectors of the premotor and primary motor cortices are engaged in a roughly somatotopic manner during the observation of body-part-specifi c movements (Buccino et al., 2001 ;

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

7

Filimon, Nelson, Hagler, & Sereno, 2007 ; Jastorff , Begliomini, Fabbri-Destro, Rizzolatti, & Orban, 2010 ; Sakreida, Schubotz, Wolfensteller, & von Cramon, 2005 ; Wheaton, Thompson, Syngeniotis, Abbott, & Puce, 2004 ). And while it is less clear whether these regions also facilitate perception, supportive evidence is beginning to accrue (Michael et al., 2014 ; Serino, De Filippo, Casavecchia, Coccia, Shiff rar, & Ladavas, 2010 ).

Turning to more interpretive aspects of action observation, in Chapter 7 Hickok summarizes a study by Tranel, Kemmerer, Adolphs, Damasio, and Damasio ( 2003 ) in which ninety brain-damaged patients with widely distributed left- or right-hemisphere lesions were given the following two tasks, both of which probe non-verbal knowledge of action concepts: (1) Picture Attribute, in which, for each item, the subject is shown two photographs of actions and must indicate which one satisfi es a certain value for a single attribute (e.g., whether swinging on a swingset or sliding down a slide would be more tiring); and (2) Picture Comparison, in which, for each

Fig. 2. Frontal and parietal sites where TMS causally aff ected various aspects of the perception and understanding of observed actions. In the study by Catmur et al. ( 2011 ), the ventral and dorsal frontal sites were stimulated in the right hemisphere but are represented here on the left hemisphere. The white lines indicate the frontal and parietal nodes of the ‘action observation network’ that is based on Caspers et al.’s ( 2010 ) meta-analysis of fMRI studies. Complete references to the TMS studies cited here can be found in Avenanti, Candidi, and Urgesi ( 2013 ). (from Avenanti et al., 2013 , p. 3; reproduced with permission).

david kemmerer

8

Fig. 3. Clusters of voxels where signifi cant associations were found between lesion sites and disorders involving various aspects of the perception and understanding of observed actions. The results are based on an anatomic likelihood estimation meta-analysis of 11 lesion-symptom mapping studies encompassing 361 brain-damaged patients. (A) Axial slices, where the left hemisphere is on the left. (B) 3D rendering of the Montreal Neurological Institute (MNI) template. Note that deeper regions, especially for the IPS, are projected onto the surface of the template. MTG = middle temporal gyrus; IFG = inferior frontal gyrus; IPS = intraparietal sulcus (from Urgesi et al., 2014 , p. 9; reproduced with permission).

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

9

item, the subject is shown three photographs of actions and must indicate which one is diff erent in kind from the other two (e.g., sewing a sock, sewing a button, or threading a needle). The researchers found that twenty-six patients failed one or both tasks, and when they contrasted the lesion sites of these impaired patients against those of the sixty-four unimpaired patients, they discovered that the greatest lesion overlap specifi c to the impaired patients was in the left inferior frontoparietal cortex and underlying white matter, as well as in the white matter beneath the left pSTS and posterior middle temporal gyrus (pMTG). In discussing these results, Hickok argues that while the involvement of the pSTS/pMTG does constitute evidence that this region subserves critical aspects of action concepts, the involvement of the inferior frontoparietal territory merely refl ects task demands, such as having to imagine the dynamic motion properties of the statically portrayed actions, or having to draw inferences about their relationships along various dimensions. This account in terms of task demands is open to criticism, however.

First, in a later study involving seventy-eight patients, Tranel, Manzel, Asp, and Kemmerer ( 2008 ) used not only static photographs but also dynamic video clips in two parallel action naming tasks that do not require as much inferential processing as the Picture Attribute and Picture Comparison tasks employed in the previous study. Importantly, they still found that impaired performance, regardless of stimulus type, was linked with a pattern of lesion sites very similar to the one reported by Tranel et al. ( 2003 ). Second, in another study involving 147 patients, Kemmerer et al. ( 2012 ) used six tasks: Picture Attribute, Picture Comparison, Static Action Naming, and three tasks requiring verb comprehension – specifi cally, Word–Picture Matching (in which a single verb must be matched with one of two photographs of actions), Word Attribute (analogous to Picture Attribute, only with verbs as stimuli), and Word Comparison (analogous to Picture Comparison, only with verbs as stimuli). As in the earlier experiments, the defi cit-lesion correlations across tasks implicated not only the left pSTS/pMTG, but also, and more consistently, the left IFC. Third, similar results have emerged from several other lesion studies that have explored the neural underpinnings of action concepts ( Figure 3 ). And fourth, there is converging evidence from TMS that the IFC contributes not only to the perception of observed actions (as discussed above), but also to the higher-level conceptual processing of their sequential and goal-directed properties (Cattaneo, Sandrini, & Schwarzbach, 2010 ; Clerget, Winderickx, Fadiga, & Olivier, 2009 ; Jacquet & Avenanti, in press ). Taken together, these fi ndings suggest that, contrary to Hickok’s view, the left inferior frontoparietal territory does not simply fulfi ll general task demands when actions must be recognized and categorized; instead, it appears to contribute to the actual content of the relevant concepts. More precisely, this territory may underlie some of the motor features of action concepts, while

david kemmerer

10

the pSTS/pMTG may underlie their visual motion features (Kemmerer et al., 2008 ; Kemmerer, 2012 , 2014 ).

On the other hand, I think Hickok is right to highlight a number of neuropsychological conditions in which action production is disrupted but action understanding is apparently preserved. For example, in Chapter 4 he points out that even though some patients with limb apraxia display corresponding execution and comprehension impairments for actions involving tools, others have defi cits that are restricted to execution (e.g., Halsband, Schmitt, Weyers, Binkofski, Grützner, & Freund, 2001 ; Negri, Rumiati, Zadini, Ukmar, Mahon, & Caramazza, 2007 ; Pazzaglia, Smania, Corato, & Aglioti, 2008 ). He also indicates in Chapter 4 that individuals with Moebius syndrome are quite good at recognizing facial expressions of emotion despite being congenitally incapable of moving the muscles that generate such expressions (Bogart & Matsumoto, 2010 ). And in Chapter 6 he notes that while people who suff er from amyotrophic lateral sclerosis or cerebral palsy gradually lose much of their own motor control, they seem to retain the ability to fathom other people’s behavior, as illustrated by famous fi gures like the physicist Stephen Hawking and the novelist Christopher Nolan.

Hickok correctly argues that these sorts of dissociations between impaired action production and spared action understanding challenge the hypothesis that in order to make sense of other people’s movements it is absolutely necessary to simulate them in one’s own motor system. This does not entail, however, that motor simulation never adds anything meaningful to action understanding. After all, if that were the case, it would be extremely diffi cult, if not impossible, to account for all of the TMS and lesion data described above. Moreover, it would leave unexplained a variety of interesting results involving expertise eff ects.

In particular, several studies have shown that in the domains of dance (Calvo-Merino, Grèzes, Glaser, Passingham, & Haggard, 2006 ; Cross, Hamilton, Kraemer, Kelley, & Grafton, 2009a ; Cross, Kraemer, De, Hamilton, Kelley, & Grafton, 2009b ) and basketball (Aglioti, Cesari, Romani, & Urgesi, 2008 ), during action observation the mirror system is modulated signifi cantly more by motor expertise than visual expertise. In addition, a recent experiment involving soccer demonstrated that the ability to predict the outcomes of penalty kicks is disrupted by TMS to the dorsal premotor cortex in skilled players but not in novices, thereby suggesting that highly refi ned motor knowledge in a specifi c domain can causally infl uence one’s perceptual discrimination of actions in that domain ( Makris & Urgesi, in press ). Hickok addresses the topic of expertise eff ects in Chapter 7, but he does not consider any of the studies cited here. Instead, he proposes, in keeping with his purely associative view of the mirror system, that even though one’s motor cortex may resonate to the sight of specialized actions that one is able to perform,

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

11

such responses “are not the cause of the richer understanding while watching, they are a consequence of understanding the scenario more richly, which often boils down to having more sensory experience” (p. 155, emphasis in original). It is not clear, however, how this approach can accommodate the fi ndings just mentioned (see also Casile & Giese, 2006 ).

A fi nal issue that warrants discussion is whether the mirror system contributes to understanding the intentions that motivate other people’s actions. In Chapter 4, Hickok summarizes a frequently cited single-cell recording study by Rizzolatti’s team in which macaque monkeys both executed and observed two types of kinematically similar but intentionally diff erent actions: fi rst, reaching and grasping objects with the intention of placing them in a container; and second, reaching and grasping objects with the intention of eating them (Fogassi, Ferrari, Gesierich, Rozzi, Chersi, & Rizzolatti, 2005 ). The researchers found that some cells in the parietal lobe had fi ring patterns that appeared to distinguish between the specifi c intentions of the movements, regardless of whether they were executed or observed, and before the target objects were contacted by the hand. Hickok rightly points out, however, that the experimental design had a confound, because the presence/absence of the container served as a contextual cue regarding the agent’s ultimate aim, with presence signaling the intention to place the objects in the container, and absence signaling the intention to eat them. Thus, in response to the question “How did the monkey’s neurons predict the goal?”, Hickok answers “It was the non motoric context, not the observed movement” (p. 69, emphasis in original).

More recent research, though, supports the view that, at least in some situations, both the frontal and the parietal components of the human mirror system are sensitive to subtle kinematic features that convey information about the intentions behind observed actions (e.g., Becchio, Cavallo, Begliomini, Sartori, Feltrin, & Castiello, 2012 ; Lestou, Pollick, & Kourtzi, 2008 ; Vingerhoets, Honoré, Vandekerckhove, Nys, Vandemaele, & Achten, 2010 ; for a review see Ansuini, Cavallo, Bertone, & Bechio, in press ). For example, on each trial of Becchio et al.’s ( 2012 ) fMRI study, subjects fi rst saw an object-grasping movement that had either a social intent (to compete or cooperate) or a non-social intent (to act independently), and then they judged whether a static photograph depicted a continuation of the observed action. Despite the lack of contextual cues, the observation of movements with social intent engaged the IFC and the supramarginal gyrus to a greater degree than the observation of movements with non-social intent. What’s more, relative to perceived non-social grasping, perceived social grasping recruited two components of the so-called mentalizing system – specifi cally, the dorsomedial prefrontal cortex and the temporoparietal junction (the other components of this network are the precuneus and the anterolateral temporal cortex). This is

david kemmerer

12

especially interesting because the mentalizing system has been associated with a wide range of tasks that involve explicitly, deliberately determining ‘why’ actions are performed (Schurtz, Radua, Aichhorn, Richlan, & Perner, 2014 ; Van Overwalle, 2009 ). In contrast, even though the mirror system seems to be at least somewhat involved in decoding intentions, it has been linked more strongly with representing ‘how’ actions are performed (Spunt & Lieberman, 2012 ; Van Overwalle & Baetens, 2009 ). Although Hickok does talk briefl y about the mentalizing system in Chapter 9, it is somewhat surprising that he does not directly compare the diff erent ways in which this system and the mirror system contribute to action understanding.

3 . Comprehending l inguistically represented actions I suggested above that the motor components of action concepts may be represented, in part, in motor-related frontal and parietal regions. During the past few years, this issue has received a great deal of attention because it bears directly on the neural substrates of the meanings of action verbs and sentences. But even though the literature on this topic is now fairly large, the fundamental issue remains quite controversial (for reviews and perspectives see Kemmerer & Gonzalez-Castillo, 2010 ; Kemmerer, 2012 , 2014 , in press; Papeo, Pascual-Leone, & Caramazza, 2013 ; Pulvermüller, 2005 , 2013 ; Rueschemeyer & Bekkering, 2013 ; Taylor & Zwaan, 2009 ; Tomasino & Rumiati, 2013 ). In Chapters 6 and 7, Hickok maintains that the motor features of action verbs and sentences do not depend on the precentral motor cortices, but I hope to show that many of his arguments can be challenged.

One of Hickok’s lines of attack proceeds as follows (pp. 135–136, emphasis in original): “The movements themselves, as they are coded in motor cortex, are semantically ambiguous and therefore meaningless. The very same motor program that results in lifting a pitcher and pouring liquid into a cup could mean POUR or FILL depending on whether we conceptualize the act from the perspective of the pitcher or the cup … The meanings simply aren’t in the movements, and the closer you get to motor codes for specifi c movements, such as primary motor cortex, the farther removed from meaning you get.”

First of all, it is certainly true that the same objective scenario can be described in diff erent ways, but Hickok seems to be unaware of the fact that I myself have investigated how this phenomenon might be related to the mirror system (Kemmerer & Gonzalez-Castillo, 2010 ; see also Kemmerer, 2006 ). The complete analysis is rather complex, but the short story goes roughly like this. Pour and fi ll are actually the names of two diff erent subclasses of the large class of English ‘putting’ verbs (Levin, 1993 ). Pour verbs (e.g., dribble , drip , drop , dump , spill ) share an event structure template that can be broadly

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

13

characterized as ‘X causes Y to go to Z in some manner’, whereas fi ll verbs (e.g., decorate , drench , encrust , saturate , shroud ) share an event structure template that can be broadly characterized as ‘X causes Z to change state by means of adding Y’. It is because of these contrasting templates that the two subclasses of verbs occur in contrasting argument structure constructions: pour water into the cup versus *fi ll water into the cup , and *pour the cup with water vs. fi ll the cup with water. The two templates vary with respect to which entity is treated as the main ‘target’ of the action – the thing that changes location, or the thing that changes state – and these semantic diff erences regarding the relative prominence of the participants in the hierarchical goal structures of the templates correspond isomorphically to syntactic diff erences regarding the relative prominence of the noun phrases in the hierarchical grammatical structures of the constructions. For present purposes, what matters most is that the relevant template-level motor features of verb meaning capture high-level, diff erentially construable aspects of action representation that involve the goals and intentions of agents, and there is some evidence they depend on the left IFC, most notably the posterior part of Broca’s area (for details see Kemmerer & Gonzalez-Castillo, 2010 ; see also Kemmerer, 2012 ).

Another important point has to do not so much with the semantic features that are shared by all the members of a particular (sub)class of verbs, but instead with the semantic features that are unique to individual verbs. Many action verbs do not elaborate the motor components of their meanings in very much detail. For example, after surveying approximately 1,900 English action verbs involving the thematic role commonly known as ‘instrument’, Koenig, Mauner, Bienvenue, and Conklin (2008, p. 175) conclude that “verbs that require or allow instruments constrain the end states of the situations they describe more than they constrain the agent’s initial activity”. It is also the case, however, that many action verbs do specify categories of bodily movements that are defi ned rather narrowly (e.g., squint , nibble , pinch , kneel , tiptoe ; for data on cross-linguistic diversity, see Filipovic, 2007 ; Levinson & Wilkins, 2006 ; Malt, Gennari, Imai, Ameel, Tsuda, & Majid, 2008 ; Slobin, 2000 , 2006 ). The question, then, is whether the motor components of such semantically idiosyncratic verbs rely on the precentral motor cortices. Based on the passage from Hickok that I quoted above, it would appear that he is skeptical. Yet that passage seems to confl ict with an earlier one in the same chapter, where he acknowledges that “sensory and motor systems perform abstract, complex computations” (p. 128, my emphasis). It is also noteworthy that although Hickok focuses mainly on the primary motor cortex throughout his discussion of action concepts (pp. 131, 136, 137, 159, 174), the majority of experimental studies have concentrated more on the premotor cortex, which is widely believed to support a greater degree of schematization.

david kemmerer

14

Continuing with this theme, numerous fMRI studies have shown that tasks such as reading action verbs (e.g., Hauk, Johnsrude, & Pulvermüller, 2004 ), hearing action verbs (e.g., Raposo, Moss, Stamatakis, & Tyler, 2009 ), making semantic similarity judgments about action verbs (e.g., Kemmerer et al., 2008 ), and distinguishing action verbs from non-words (e.g., de Grauwe, Willems, Rueschemeyer, Lemhöfer, & Schriefers, 2014) tend to evoke more or less somatotopically organized responses in premotor and/or primary motor areas. In considering such fi ndings, Hickok expresses several concerns.

One is that when the verb-induced activation peaks from multiple studies are plotted in relation to cytoarchitectonically defi ned premotor and primary motor regions, many of them fall beyond the boundaries of both areas (de Zubicaray, Archiuli, & McMahon, 2013). This worry is mitigated, however, by the fact that the premotor and primary motor regions have also been defi ned on the basis of functional neuroimaging data (Mayka, Corcos, Leurgans, & Vaillancourt, 2006 ), and when numerous verb-induced activation peaks are plotted on these maps instead, most if not all of them fall inside the boundaries of the two areas (see Figure 4 ; Kemmerer & Gonzalez-Castillo, 2010 ; Kemmerer et al., 2012 ). Additional research is needed to determine which approach to defi ning the regions is more appropriate. But it is noteworthy that – completely apart from the defi nitional debate, and perhaps of greater importance – several studies have used functional localizer scans to verify that some of the motor areas that are engaged when subjects process body-part-specifi c action verbs are also engaged when they execute correspondingly body-part-specifi c movements (e.g., Desai, Binder, Conant, & Seidenberg, 2010 ; Hauk et al., 2004 ; Moody-Triantis, Humphreys, & Gennari, 2014 ; Raposo et al., 2009 ).

Another concern of Hickok’s is that, according to a recent meta-analysis by Watson, Cardillo, Ianni, and Chatterjee ( 2013 ), some fMRI studies have found that action verbs do not elicit any signifi cant responses whatsoever in the precentral motor cortices. But while this may appear to undermine the hypothesis that the motor features of verb meanings are represented in the precentral motor cortices, it does so only if one assumes that those features must always be accessed when action verbs are processed. A close look at the literature on this topic reveals a considerable amount of variability. On the one hand, several studies employing either electrophysiology or magnetoencephalography have found that verbs for leg/foot actions, arm/hand actions, and face/mouth actions not only trigger the expected topographic response patterns in the precentral motor cortices, but do so extremely quickly – in some cases within approximately 200 ms post stimulus onset (Dalla Volta, Fabbri-Destro, & Gentilucci, 2014 ; Hauk & Pulvermüller, 2004 ; Klepp et al., 2014 ; Pulvermüller, Shtyrov, & Illoniemi, 2005b ), and in other cases even faster, as soon as 80 ms after the words can be uniquely identifi ed (Shtyrov, Butorina, Nikolaeva, & Stroganova, 2014 ). But while these fi ndings

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

15

suggest that action verbs engage the precentral motor cortices automatically, a growing number of other results support the alternative view that this process is strongly infl uenced by both task and context. Here are just two examples. In a TMS study, Papeo, Vallesi, Isja, and Rumiati ( 2009 ) found that although the level of activity in hand-related primary motor cortex was enhanced when participants were instructed to think about the motor features of hand-related verbs, it was not enhanced when participants were instructed to count the number of syllables in the very same words. And in an fMRI study, Raposo et al. ( 2009 ) found that although somatotopically mapped motor areas were engaged when participants heard action verbs in isolation (e.g., kick ) and in literal phrases (e.g., kick the ball ), they were not engaged when participants heard such verbs in idiomatic phrases (e.g., kick the bucket ) (for similar results see Aziz-Zadeh, Wilson, Rizzolatti, & Iacoboni, 2006 , Desai, Conant, Binder, Park, & Seidenberg, 2013 , and Schuil, Smits, & Zwaan, 2013 , but for contrary results see Boulenger, Hauk, & Pulvermüller, 2009 ). These studies, among others (Aravena et al., 2014 ; Aravena et al., 2012 ;

Fig. 4. Activation peaks in left primary motor and premotor cortices reported by some of the fMRI studies that have investigated the neural substrates of the motor features of verbs and sentences encoding leg/foot-related actions (green circles), arm/hand-related actions (light blue circles), and face/mouth-related actions (red circles). Activations are plotted on an infl ated brain with boundaries for the primary motor cortex (dark blue) and premotor cortex (yellow) based on Mayka et al.’s ( 2006 ) Human Motor Area Template. Complete references to the fMRI studies from which activation data were drawn can be found in Kemmerer et al. ( 2012 ) (from Kemmerer et al., 2012 , p. 843; reproduced with permission).

david kemmerer

16

Mirabella, Iaconelli, Spadacenta, Federico, & Gallese, 2012 ; Papeo, Rumiati, Cecchetto, & Tomasino, 2012 ; Sato, Mengarelli, Riggio, Gallese, & Buccino, 2008 ), suggest that verb-induced motor activation is not a rigid, infl exible aff air, but is instead sensitive to attentional and situational factors that are only beginning to be understood. It is essential to realize, however, that the mere fact that there is some variability regarding when and how the motor features of verb meanings are retrieved does not imply that those features are not really long-term components of the concepts, or that they are not really subserved by the precentral motor cortices. After all, as Lebois, Wilson-Mendenhall, and Barsalou (in press) recently demonstrated, variability in conceptual grounding eff ects – i.e., in behavioral and neural markers of the retrieval of modality-specifi c representations during conceptual processing – is far more common than often assumed, and even the most entrenched features of concepts are not always activated in an immediate, automatic manner (see also Binder & Desai, 2011 ; Willems & Casasanto, 2011 ; Willems & Fracken, 2012 ; Zwaan, 2014 ).

Finally, Hickok echoes Mahon and Caramazza ( 2008 ) in arguing that even when action verbs do engage the precentral motor cortices, this may not be functionally relevant to comprehension. To support such a position, he refers once again to individuals who have reduced motor capacities but are nevertheless able to use action verbs. For instance, he points out that Stephen Hawking “has severe motor dysfunction, yet understands verbs well enough to function at a very high intellectual level” (p. 138). In keeping with this view, a few recent neuropsychological studies have found that, indeed, disturbances involving the precentral motor cortices do not always aff ect the comprehension of action verbs (Arévalo, Baldo, & Dronkers, 2012 ; Kemmerer, Miller, MacPherson, Huber, & Tranel, 2013 ). It is possible, however, that in all of these cases relatively good performance could be achieved by relying mainly on various non-motor aspects of verb meanings, such as their visual motion properties, which are most likely represented in the left pSTS/pMTG (see the previous section, as well as Kemmerer, 2014). Such a strategy may not always be suffi cient, though. As indicated above, when Kemmerer et al. ( 2012 ) administered three diff erent verb comprehension tasks to 147 brain-damaged patients with widely distributed left- or right-hemisphere lesions, they found that defi cits were linked not only with lesions in the left pSTS/pMTG, but also, and more consistently, with lesions in the left IFC. Moreover, across all three tasks, defi cits were also related to damage in putatively hand-related sectors of the precentral motor cortices. These latter results dovetail nicely with several TMS studies which have shown that by briefl y perturbing hand-related motor regions, one can, depending on the details of the protocol, either facilitate (Pulvermüller, Hauk, Nikulin, & Ilmoniemi, 2005a ) or disrupt (Gerfo, Oliveri, Torriero, Salerno, Koch, &

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

17

Caltagirone, 2008 ; Kuipers, van Koningsbruggen, & Thierry, 2013 ; Repetto, Columbo, Cipresso, & Riva, 2013 ) the processing of hand-related action verbs. Of course, no experiment is perfect, and both Papeo et al. ( 2013 ) and Hickok rightly point out that some of these TMS studies have limitations. Collectively, however, they bolster the hypothesis that, contrary to Hickok’s position, the precentral motor cortices play genuinely causal roles in the comprehension of linguistically expressed actions (for additional data involving expertise eff ects, see Beilock, Lyons, Mattarella-Micke, Nusbaum, & Small, 2008 ; Locatelli, Gatti, & Tettamanti, 2012 ; Lyons, Mattarella-Micke, Cieslak, Nusbaum, & Small, 2010 ).

4 . Perceiving speech In Chapter 5, Hickok focuses on the controversial question of whether the articulatory system contributes not only to speech production but also to speech perception. He discusses this issue in depth because, in his opinion, “the speech domain has become the ultimate test case for the viability of the action understanding interpretation of mirror neurons” (p. 91). Although I do not believe that this particular domain really has such a special status, I nevertheless think that Chapter 5 is one of the best in the book, largely because Hickok is intimately familiar with the material and hence is on very solid ground, having devoted much of his career to investigating, from both empirical and theoretical perspectives, the neural underpinnings of speech processing (Hickok & Poeppel, 2007 ; Hickok, Houde, & Rong, 2011 ; Hickok, 2012 , 2014a , 2014b ).

He begins by recounting the rise and fall of the motor theory of speech perception during the 30-year period between the late 1950s and late 1980s. In short, this theory maintains that we do not recognize speech sounds according to their acoustic patterns, but rather according to their articulatory patterns. Hickok deftly describes how this bold proposal gradually gained support in psycholinguistics but then lost favor when it was forced to confront a series of challenging fi ndings, such as that both prelingual infants and non-lingual chinchillas are able to perceive speech sounds like /ta/ and /da/ in a categorical manner, despite being unable to produce them. By the early 1990s, the motor theory no longer had many proponents. It was quickly resurrected, however, after the discovery of mirror neurons, and ever since then a steady stream of brain mapping studies has been exploring the extent to which speech perception is subserved not only by superior temporal areas for auditory processing, but also by frontal motor areas for articulatory control. At fi rst, Hickok admits that some of these studies “are impressive and in isolation appear to provide strong support for the motor theory of speech perception” (p. 91). But then he proceeds to expose a number of mostly methodological

david kemmerer

18

shortcomings of several studies, and also claims that a handful of other experiments “are open to a similar kind of critique: they use partially ambiguous stimuli, fail to account for response bias, and use artifi cial tasks that don’t necessarily tap into processes that are used under normal, everyday speech listening conditions” (p. 101). To reinforce his position that frontal motor areas are not causally involved in ordinary speech perception, he goes on to review several lines of neuropsychological research – including some fascinating work from his own lab – showing that although disturbances of articulatory control can interfere with phoneme discrimination and identifi cation tasks that require close attention to the speech sounds themselves, they do not impair the ability to perform spoken word comprehension tasks, like matching the word bear with a picture of a bear, even when the array of distractors includes pictures of objects with similar-sounding names (e.g., a pear). Based on such data, as well as on the older results from infants and chinchillas, Hickok concludes that “when you take the motor speech system out of the picture the ability to perceive speech sounds remains unaff ected. The motor theory of speech perception is (still) wrong” (p. 109).

To be sure, Hickok makes a powerful case that the motor theory of speech perception places too much weight on the articulatory component and too little weight on the auditory component. I am not entirely convinced, however, that he is right to downplay the importance of the articulatory component as much as he does. For one thing, it may not be such a serious problem that the vast majority of brain mapping studies which have found frontal motor areas to be involved in speech perception have used tasks that force subjects to explicitly detect subtle phonemic contrasts (besides the studies cited by Hickok, see Bartoli, D’Ausilio, Berry, Badino, Bever, & Fadiga, in press ; Callan, Callan, & Jones, 2014 ; Du, Buchsbaum, Grady, & Alain, 2014 ; Liebenthal, Sabri, Beardsley, Mangalathu-Arumana, & Desai, 2013 ; Rogers, Möttönen, Boyles, & Watkins, 2014 ; Sehm et al., 2013 ). This is because there are actually many situations in daily life when one hears utterances with moderate to low intelligibility – for instance, when listening to a talker in a loud environment, or when listening to a talker who has a heavy accent or a speech impediment – and it certainly seems worthwhile to know that in such circumstances one’s own articulatory system is recruited to facilitate perception, perhaps by using motorically based internal models in a top-down manner to compensate for degraded bottom-up sensory representations (Davis & Johnsrude, 2007 ; also, for evidence that the engagement of articulatory cortical areas during demanding laboratory-based speech discrimination tasks cannot be explained by response bias, see Smalle, Rogers, & Möttönen, in press ).

Furthermore, two recent studies indicate that even when people do not need to perform eff ortful tasks in response to speech sounds, frontal motor regions are engaged in ways that causally infl uence perception. In the fi rst

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

19

study, Möttönen, Dutton, and Watkins ( 2013 ) exploited the well-established fact that, completely independent of attention and task demands, occasional changes in sound sequences trigger an electrophysiological eff ect called the mismatch negativity (MMN), which is generated in the auditory cortex 100–200 ms after stimulus onset (Näätänen, Tervaniemi, Sussman, Paavilainen, & Winkler, 2001 ). Each experiment began by applying a 15-minute train of TMS pulses to either the lip representation or the hand representation in the left primary motor cortex, thereby reducing the excitability of the targeted representation for at least 15 minutes after the end of stimulation. Next, subjects watched a silent fi lm, and while they were focusing their attention on the movie, they heard sound sequences consisting of frequent /da/ syllables and infrequent /ba/ and /ga/ syllables. The main fi nding was that TMS-induced disruption of the motor lip representation, but not of the motor hand representation, signifi cantly decreased the MMNs elicited by both of the infrequent syllables. This supports the view that the articulatory system normally contributes to the automatic discrimination of speech sounds. It is noteworthy, however, that disruption of the motor lip representation impaired the processing of not only the lip-related /ba/ syllables, but also the non-lip-related /ga/ syllables, suggesting a non-specifi c eff ect.

In the second study, Möttönen, van de Ven, and Watkins ( 2014 ) explored this issue further by combining TMS with magnetoencephalography. The subjects heard two sequences of speech sounds – one consisting of alternating /ba/ and /da/ syllables, and another consisting of alternating /da/ and /ga/ syllables – in two diff erent conditions: one in which they were instructed to attend to a silent fi lm, and another in which they saw the same silent fi lm but were instructed to attend to the speech sounds. Once again, when the speech stimuli were ignored, TMS-induced disruption of the motor lip representation interfered with perception in a general manner, modulating the bilateral auditory cortex responses to both the /ba/–/da/ sequence and the /da/–/ga/ sequence, starting around 170 ms after sound onset. On the other hand, when the speech stimuli were attended, TMS-induced disruption of the motor lip representation interfered with perception in an articulator-specifi c manner, with signifi cantly greater left-lateralized modulation of the /ba/–/da/ sequence than the /da/–/ga/ sequence, starting as early as 60–100 ms after sound onset.

Taken together, the results of these two studies provide compelling evidence that, contrary to Hickok’s view, even when people don’t concentrate directly on the speech signals that they’re hearing, their articulatory system contributes to their perception. Moreover, when people do focus on those sounds, the top-down infl uence of frontal motor areas is both highly refi ned and extremely rapid (see also Lametti, Rochet-Capellan, Neufeld, Shiller, & Ostroy, 2014 ).

david kemmerer

20

5 . Conclusion I applaud Hickok for cutting through all the hype surrounding mirror neurons. However, I think he has gone too far in his critique, to the extent that he has thrown the proverbial baby out with the bathwater. As I have shown here, a growing literature strongly suggests that motor regions in the frontal and parietal lobes not only subserve the execution of actions, but also play genuinely functional roles in the perception and understanding of actions, regardless of whether they are directly observed or linguistically represented. In addition, recent research indicates that although the articulatory system is involved primarily in speech production, it enhances speech perception too, even in the absence of explicit attention to the auditory stimuli. Of course, many questions remain unanswered, but they will most likely be worked out in the coming years, since the fi eld of mirror neuron research is actually much healthier than Hickok seems to realize.

references Aglioti , S. M. , Cesari , P. , Romani , M. , & Urgesi , C . ( 2008 ). Action anticipation and motor

resonance in elite basketball players . Nature Neuroscience , 11 , 1109 – 1116 . Ansuini , C. , Cavallo , A. , Bertone , C. , & Becchio , C . (in press). Intentions in the brain: the

unveiling of Mister Hyde . Neuroscientist . Aravena , P. , Courson , M. , Frak , V. , Cheylus , A. , Paulignan , Y. , Deprez , V. , & Nazir , T . ( 2014 ).

Action relevance in linguistic context drives word-induced motor activity . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 8 , 163 .

Aravena , P. , Delevoye-Turrell , Y. , Deprez , V. , Cheylus , A. , Paulignan , Y. , Frak , V. , & Nazir , T . ( 2012 ). Grip force reveals the context sensitivity of language-induced motor activity during ‘action word’ processing: evidence from sentential negation . PLoS ONE , 7 , e50287 .

Arévalo , A. , Baldo , J. V. , & Dronkers , N. F . ( 2012 ). What do brain lesions tell us about theories of embodied semantics and the human mirror neuron system? Cortex , 48 , 242 – 254 .

Avenanti , A. , Candidi , M. , & Urgesi , C . ( 2013 ). Vicarious motor activation during action perception: beyond correlational evidence . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7 , 185 .

Aziz-Zadeh , L. , Wilson , S. M. , Rizzolatti , G. , & Iacoboni , M . ( 2006 ). Congruent embodied representations for visually presented actions and linguistic phrases describing actions . Current Biology , 16 , 1818 – 1823 .

Barchiesi , G. , & Cattaneo , L . ( 2013 ). Early and late motor responses to action observation . Social, Cognitive, and Aff ective Neuroscience , 8 , 711 – 719 .

Barsalou , L. W . ( 2013 ). Mirroring as pattern completion inferences within situated conceptualizations . Cortex , 49 , 2951 – 2953 .

Bartoli , E. , D’Ausilio , A. , Berry , J. , Badino , L. , Bever , T. , & Fadiga , L . (in press). Listener–speaker perceived distance predicts the degree of contribution to speech perception . Cerebral Cortex .

Becchio , C. , Cavallo , A. , Begliomini , C. , Sartori , L. , Feltrin , G. , & Castiello , U . ( 2012 ). Social grasping: from mirroring to mentalizing . NeuroImage , 61 , 240 – 248 .

Beilock , S. L. , Lyons , I. M. , Mattarella-Micke , A. , Nusbaum , H. C. , & Small , S. L . ( 2008 ). Sports experience changes the neural processing of action language . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 105 , 13269 – 13273 .

Binder , J. R. , & Desai , R. H . ( 2011 ). The neurobiology of semantic memory . Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15 , 527 – 536 .

Bogart , K. R. , & Matsumoto , D . ( 2010 ). Facial mimicry is not necessary to recognize emotion: facial expression recognition by people with Moebius syndrome . Social Neuroscience , 5 , 241 – 251 .

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

21

Boulenger , V. , Hauk , O. , & Pulvermüller , F . ( 2009 ). Grasping ideas with the motor system: semantic somatotopy in idiom comprehension . Cerebral Cortex , 19 , 1905 – 1914 .

Buccino , G. , Binkofski , F. , Fink , G. R. , Fadiga , L. , Fogassi , L. , Gallese , V. , Seitz , R. J. , Zilles , K. , Rizzolatti , G. , & Freund , H. J . ( 2001 ). Action observation activates premotor and parietal areas in a somatotopic manner: an fMRI study . European Journal of Neuroscience , 13 , 400 – 404 .

Callan , D. , Callan , A. , & Jones , J. A . ( 2014 ). Speech motor brain regions are diff erentially recruited during perception of native and foreign-accented phonemes for fi rst and second language listeners . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 8 , 275 .

Calvo-Merino , B. , Grèzes , J. , Glaser , D. E. , Passingham , R. E. , & Haggard , P . ( 2006 ). Seeing or doing? Infl uence of visual and motor familiarity in action observation . Current Biology , 16 , 1905 – 1910 .

Casile , A. , & Giese , M. A . ( 2006 ). Nonvisual motor training infl uences biological motion perception . Current Biology , 16 , 69 – 74 .

Caspers , S. , Zilles , K. , Laird , A. R. , & Eickhoff , S. B . ( 2010 ). ALE meta-analysis of action observation and imitation in the human brain . Neuroimage , 50 , 1148 – 1167 .

Catmur , C. , Walsh , V. , & Heyes , C . ( 2007 ). Sensorimotor learning confi gures the human mirror system . Current Biology , 17 , 1527 – 1531 .

Cattaneo , L. , Sandrini , M. , & Schwarzbach , J . ( 2010 ). State-dependent TMS reveals a hierarchical representation of observed acts in the temporal, parietal, and premotor cortices . Cerebral Cortex , 20 , 2252 – 2258 .

Clerget , E. , Winderickx , A. , Fadiga , L. , & Olivier , E . ( 2009 ). Role of Broca’s area in encoding sequential human actions: a virtual lesion study . Neuroreport , 20 , 1496 – 1499 .

Cook , R. , Bird , G. , Catmur , C. , Press , C. , & Heyes , C . ( 2014 ). Mirror neurons: from origin to function . Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 37 , 177 – 241 .

Cross , E. S. , Hamilton , A. , Kraemer , D. J. M. , Kelley , W. M. , & Grafton , S. T . ( 2009 a). Dissociable substrates for body motion and physical experience in the human action observation network . European Journal of Neuroscience , 30 , 1383 – 1392 .

Cross , E. S. , Kraemer , D. J. M. , De , A. F. , Hamilton , A. , Kelley , W. M. , & Grafton , S. T . ( 2009 b). Sensitivity of the action observation network to physical and observational learning . Cerebral Cortex , 19 , 315 – 326 .

Dalla Volta , R. , Fabbri-Destro , M. , & Gentilucci , M . ( 2014 ). Spatiotemporal dynamics during processing of abstract and concrete verbs: an ERP study . Neuropsychologia , 61 , 163 – 174 .

Damasio , A. , & Meyer , K . ( 2008 ). Behind the looking glass . Nature , 454 , 167 – 168 . Davis , M. H. , & Johnsrude , I. S . ( 2007 ). Hearing speech sounds: top-down infl uences on the

interface between audition and speech perception . Hearing Research , 229 , 132 – 147 . De Grauwe , S. , Willems , R. M. , Rueschemeyer , S. A. , Lemhöfer , K. , & Schriefers , H . ( 2014 ).

Embodied language in fi rst- and second-language speakers: neural correlates of processing motor verbs . Neuropsychologia , 56 , 334 – 349 .

Desai , R. , Binder , J. R. , Conant , L. L. , & Seidenberg , M. S . ( 2010 ). Activation of sensory-motor areas in sentence comprehension . Cerebral Cortex , 20 , 468 – 478 .

Desai , R. , Conant , L. L. , Binder , J. R. , Park , H. , & Seidenberg , M. S . ( 2013 ). A piece of the action: modulation of sensory-motor regions by action idioms and metaphors . NeuroImage , 83 , 862 – 869 .

De Zubicaray , G. , Arciuli , J. , & McMahon , K . ( 2013 ). Putting an ‘end’ to the motor cortex representations of action words . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 25 , 1957 – 1974 .

Di Pellegrino , G. , Fadiga , L. , Fogassi , L. , Gallese , V. , & Rizzolatti , G . ( 1992 ). Understanding motor events: a neurophysiological study . Experimental Brain Research , 91 , 176 – 180 .

Du , Y. , Buchsbaum , B. R. , Grady , C. L. , & Alain , C . ( 2014 ). Noise diff erentially impacts phoneme representations in the auditory and speech motor systems . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 111 , 7126 – 7131 .

Eskenazi , T. , Grosjean , M. , Humphreys , G. W. , & Knoblich , G . ( 2009 ). The role of motor simulation in action perception: a neuropsychological case study . Psychological Research , 73 , 477 – 485 .

david kemmerer

22

Filimon , F. , Nelson , J. D. , Hagler , D. J. , & Sereno , M. I . ( 2007 ). Human cortical representations for reaching: mirror neurons for execution, observation, and imagery . Neuroimage , 37 , 1315 – 1328 .

Filipovic , L . ( 2007 ). Talking about motion . Amsterdam : John Benjamins . Fitts , P. M . ( 1954 ). The information capacity of the human motor system in controlling the

amplitude of movement . Journal of Experimental Psychology , 47 , 381 – 391 . Fogassi , L. , Ferrari , P. F. , Gesierich , B. , Rozzi , S. , Chersi , F. , & Rizzolatti , G . ( 2005 ). Parietal

lobe: from action organization to intention understanding . Science , 308 , 662 – 767 . Gerfo , E. L. , Oliveri , M. , Torriero , S. , Salerno , S. , Koch , G. , & Caltagirone , C . ( 2008 ). The

infl uence of rTMS over prefrontal and motor areas in a morphological task: grammatical vs. semantic eff ects . Neuropsychologia , 46 , 764 – 770 .

Gilaie-Dotan , S. , Kanai , R. , Bahrami , B. , Rees , G. , & Saygin , A. P . ( 2013 ). Structural neural correlates of biological motion detection ability . Neuropsychologia , 51 , 457 – 463 .

Grèzes , J. , & Decety , J . ( 2001 ). Functional anatomy of execution, mental simulation, observation, and verb generation of actions: a meta-analysis . Human Brain Mapping , 12 , 1 – 19 .

Halsband , U. , Schmitt , J. , Weyers , M. , Binkofski , F. , Grützner , G. , & Freund , H. J . ( 2001 ). Recognition and imitation of pantomimed motor acts after unilateral parietal and premotor lesions: a perspective on apraxia . Neuropsychologia , 39 , 200 – 216 .

Hauk , O. , Johnsrude , I. , & Pulvermüller , F . ( 2004 ). Somatotopic representation of action words in human motor and premotor cortex . Neuron , 41 , 301 – 307 .

Hauk , O. , & Pulvermüller , F . ( 2004 ). Neurophysiological distinction of action words in the fronto-central cortex . Human Brain Mapping , 21 , 191 – 201 .

Hickok , G . ( 2012 ). Computational neuroanatomy of speech production . Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 13 , 135 – 145 .

Hickok , G . ( 2014 a). The architecture of speech production and the role of the phoneme in speech processing . Language, Cognition, and Neuroscience , 29 , 2 – 20 .

Hickok , G . ( 2014 b). Towards an integrated psycholinguistic, neurolinguistic, and sensorimotor framework for speech production . Language, Cognition, and Neuroscience , 29 , 52 – 59 .

Hickok , G. , Houde , J. , & Rong , F . ( 2011 ). Sensorimotor integration in speech processing: computational basis and neural organization . Neuron , 69 , 407 – 422 .

Hickok , G. , & Poeppel , D . ( 2007 ). The cortical organization of speech processing . Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 8 , 393 – 402 .

Jacquet , P. , & Avenanti , A . (in press). Perturbing the action observation network during perception and categorization of actions’ goals and grips: state-dependency and virtual lesion TMS eff ects . Cerebral Cortex .

Jarrett , C . ( 2012 ). Mirror neurons: the most hyped concept in neuroscience? Psychology Today , 10 December 10, 2012.

Jastorff , J. , Begliomini , C. , Fabbri-Destro , M. , Rizzolatti , G. , & Orban , G. A . ( 2010 ). Coding observed motor acts: diff erent organizational principles in the parietal and premotor cortex of humans . Journal of Neurophysiology , 104 , 128 – 140 .

Kemmerer , D . ( 2006 ). Action verbs, argument structure constructions, and the mirror neuron system . In M. Arbib (Ed.), Action to language via the mirror neuron system (pp. 347 – 373 ). Cambridge : Cambridge University Press .

Kemmerer , D . ( 2012 ). The cross-linguistic prevalence of SOV and SVO word orders refl ects the sequential and hierarchical representation of action in Broca’s area . Language and Linguistics Compass , 6 , 50 – 66 .

Kemmerer , D . ( 2014 ). Visual and motor features of action verbs: a cognitive neuroscience perspective . In de Almeida , R. G. & Manouilidou , C. (Eds.), Cognitive science perspectives on verb representation and processing . New York : Springer .

Kemmerer , D . (in press). Are the motor features of verb meanings represented in the precentral motor cortices? Yes, but within the context of a fl exible, multilevel architecture for conceptual knowledge . Psychonomic Bulletin and Review .

Kemmerer , D. , & Gonzalez-Castillo , J . ( 2010 ). The Two-Level Theory of verb meaning: an approach to integrating the semantics of action with the mirror neuron system . Brain and Language , 112 , 54 – 76 .

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

23

Kemmerer , D. , Gonzalez-Castillo , J. , Talavage , T. , Patterson , S. , & Wiley , C . ( 2008 ). Neuroanatomical distribution of fi ve semantic components of verbs: evidence from fMRI . Brain and Language , 107 , 16 – 43 .

Kemmerer , D. , Miller , L. , MacPherson , M. K. , Huber , J. , & Tranel , D . ( 2013 ). An investigation of semantic similarity judgments about action and non-action verbs in Parkinson’s disease: implications for the Embodied Cognition Framework . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7 , 146 .

Kemmerer , D. , Rudrauf , D. , Manzel , K. , & Tranel , D . ( 2012 ). Behavioral patterns and lesion sites associated with impaired processing of lexical and conceptual knowledge of actions . Cortex , 48 , 826 – 848 .

Kilner , J. M. , Friston , K. J. , & Frith , C. D . ( 2007 ). Predictive coding: an account of the mirror neuron system . Cognitive Processes , 8 , 159 – 166 .

Kilner , J. M. , & Lemon , R. N . ( 2013 ). What we know currently about mirror neurons . Current Biology , 23 , R1057 – R1062 .

Klepp , A. , Weissler , H. , Niccolai , V. , Terhalle , A. , Geisler , H. , Schnitzler , A. , & Biermann-Ruben , K . ( 2014 ). Neuromagnetic hand and foot motor sources recruited during action verb processing . Brain and Language , 128 , 41 – 52 .

Koenig , J. P. , Mauner , G. , Bienvenue , B. , & Conklin , K . ( 2008 ). What with? The anatomy of a (proto)-role . Journal of Semantics , 25 , 175 – 220 .

Kuipers , J. R. , van Koningsbruggen , M. , & Thierry , G . ( 2013 ). Semantic priming in the motor cortex: evidence from combined repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation and event-related potentials . Neuroreport , 24 , 646 – 651 .

Lametti , D. R. , Rochet-Capellan , A. , Neufeld , E. , Shiller , D. M. , & Ostroy , D. J . ( 2014 ). Plasticity in the human speech motor system drives changes in speech perception . Journal of Neuroscience , 34 , 10339 – 10346 .

Lebois , L. A. M. , Wilson-Mendenhall , C. D. , & Barsalou , L. W . (in press). Are automatic conceptual cores the gold standard of semantic processing? The context-dependence of spatial meaning in grounded congruency eff ects . Cognitive Science .

Lestou , V. , Pollick , F. E. , & Kourtzi , Z . ( 2008 ). Neural substrates for action understanding at diff erent description levels in the human brain . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 20 , 324 – 341 .

Levin , B . ( 1993 ). English verb classes and alternations . Chicago : University of Chicago Press . Levinson , S. C. , & Wilkins , D . (Eds.) ( 2006 ). Grammars of space: explorations in cognitive

diversity . Cambridge : Cambridge University Press . Liebenthal , E. , Sabri , M. , Beardsley , S. A. , Mangalathu-Arumana , J. , & Desai , A . ( 2013 ).

Neural dynamics of phonological processing in the dorsal auditory stream . Journal of Neuroscience , 33 , 15414 – 15424 .

Locatelli , M. , Gatti , R. , & Tettamanti , M . ( 2012 ). Training of manual actions improves language understanding of semantically related action sentences . Frontiers in Psychology , 3 , 547 .

Lyons , I. M. , Mattarella-Micke , A. , Cieslak , M. , Nusbaum , H. C. , & Small , S. L . ( 2010 ). The role of personal experience in the neural processing of action-related language . Brain and Language , 112 , 214 – 222 .

Mahon , B. Z. , & Caramazza , A . ( 2008 ). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content . Journal of Physiology–Paris , 102 , 59 – 70 .

Makris , S. , & Urgesi , C . (in press). Neural underpinnings of superior action prediction abilities in soccer players . Social, Cognitive, and Aff ective Neuroscience .

Malt , B. C. , Gennari , S. , Imai , M. , Ameel , E. , Tsuda , N. , & Majid , A . ( 2008 ). Talking about walking: biomechanics and the language of locomotion . Psychological Science , 19 , 232 – 240 .

Mayka , M. A. , Corcos , D. M. , Leurgans , S. E. , & Vaillancourt , D. E . ( 2006 ). Three-dimensional locations and boundaries of motor and premotor cortices as defi ned by functional brain imaging: a meta-analysis . NeuroImage , 31 , 1453 – 1474 .

Michael , J. , Sandberg , K. , Skewes , J. , Wolf , T. , Blicher , J. , Overgaard , M. , & Frith , C. D . ( 2014 ). Continuous theta-burst stimulation demonstrates a causal role of premotor homunculus in action understanding . Psychological Science , 25 , 963 – 972 .

david kemmerer

24

Mirabella , G. , Iaconelli , S. , Spadacenta , S. , Federico , P. , & Gallese , V . ( 2012 ). Processing of hand-related verbs specifi cally aff ects the planning and execution of arm reaching movements . PLoS ONE , 7 , e35403 .

Molenberghs , P. , Cunnington , R. , & Mattingley , J. B . ( 2012 ). Brain regions with mirror properties: a meta-analysis of 125 human fMRI studies . Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews , 36 , 341 – 349 .

Moody-Triantis , C. , Humphreys , G. F. , & Gennari , S. P . ( 2014 ). Hand specifi c representations in language comprehension . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 8 , 360 .

Moro , V. , Urgesi , C. , Pernigo , S. , Lanteri , P. , Pazzaglia , M. , & Aglioti , S. M . ( 2008 ). The neural basis of body action agnosia . Neuron , 60 , 235 – 246 .

Möttönen , R. , Dutton , R. , & Watkins , K. E . ( 2013 ). Auditory-motor processing of speech sounds . Cerebral Cortex , 23 , 1190 – 1197 .

Möttönen , R. , van de Ven , G. M. , & Watkins , K. E . ( 2014 ). Attention fi ne-tunes auditory-motor processing of speech sounds . Journal of Neuroscience , 34 , 4064 – 4069 .

Näätänen , R. , Tervaniemi , M. , Sussman , E. Paavilainen , P. , & Winkler , I . ( 2001 ). ‘Primitive intelligence’ in the auditory cortex . Trends in Neuroscience , 24 , 283 – 288 .

Negri , G. A. L. , Rumiati , R. I. , Zadini , A. , Ukmar , M. , Mahon , B. Z. , & Caramazza , A . ( 2007 ). What is the role of motor simulation in action and object recognition? Evidence from apraxia . Cognitive Neuropsychology , 24 , 795 – 816 .

Papeo , L. , Pascual-Leone , P. & Caramazza , A . ( 2013 ). Disrupting the brain to validate hypotheses on the neurobiology of language . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7 , 148 .

Papeo , L. , Rumiati , R. I. , Cecchetto , C. , & Tomasino , B . ( 2012 ). On-line changing of thinking about words: the eff ect of cognitive context on neural responses to verb reading . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 24 , 2348 – 2362 .

Papeo , L. , Vallesi , A. , Isaja , A. , & Rumiati , R. I . ( 2009 ). Eff ects of TMS on diff erent stages of motor and non-motor verb processing in the primary motor cortex . PLoS ONE , 4 , e4508 .

Pazzaglia , M. , Smania , N. , Corato , E. , & Aglioti , S. M . ( 2008 ). Neural underpinnings of gesture discrimination in patients with limb apraxia . Journal of Neuroscience , 28 , 3030 – 3041 .

Pobric , G. , & Hamilton , A. F . ( 2006 ). Action understanding requires the left inferior frontal cortex . Current Biology , 16 , 524 – 529 .

Pulvermüller , F . ( 2005 ). Brain mechanisms linking language and action . Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 6 , 576 – 582 .

Pulvermüller , F . ( 2013 ). How neurons make meaning: brain mechanisms for embodied and abstract-symbolic semantics . Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 17 , 458 – 470 .

Pulvermüller , F. , Hauk , O. , Nikulin , V. , & Ilmoniemi , R . ( 2005 a). Functional links between motor and language systems . European Journal of Neuroscience , 21 , 793 – 797 .

Pulvermüller , F. , Shtyrov , Y. , & Illoniemi , R . ( 2005 b). Brain signatures of meaning access in action word recognition . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 17 , 884 – 892 .

Raposo , A. , Moss , H. E. , Stamatakis , E. A. , & Tyler , L. K . ( 2009 ). Modulation of motor, premotor cortices by actions, action words, and action sentences . Neuropsychologia , 47 , 388 – 396 .

Repetto , C. , Colombo , B. , Cipresso , P. , & Riva , G . ( 2013 ). The eff ects of rTMS over the primary motor cortex: the link between action and language . Neuropsychologia , 51 , 8 – 13 .

Rizzolatti , G. , Cattaneo , L. , Fabbri-Destro , M. , & Rozzi , S . ( 2014 ). Cortical mechanisms underlying the organization of goal-directed actions and mirror neuron-based action understanding . Physiological Review , 94 , 655 – 706 .

Rogers , J. C. , Möttönen , R. , Boyles , R. , & Watkins , K. E . ( 2014 ). Discrimination of speech and non-speech sounds following theta-burst stimulation of the motor cortex . Frontiers in Psychology , 5 , 754 .

Rueschemeyer , S. A. , & Bekkering , H . ( 2013 ). Embodied lexical relations: fl exible tools for predicting the future . In Y. Coello & A. Bartolo (Eds.), Language and action in cognitive neuroscience (pp. 111 – 125 ). London : Psychology Press .

Sakreida , K. , Schubotz , R. I. , Wolfensteller , U. , & von Cramon , D. Y . ( 2005 ). Motion class dependency in observers’ motor areas revealed by functional magnetic resonance imaging . Journal of Neuroscience , 25 , 1335 – 1342 .

reflections on THE MYTH OF MIRROR NEURONS

25

Sato , M. , Mengarelli , M. , Riggio , L. , Gallese , V. , & Buccino , G . ( 2008 ). Task related modulation of the motor system during language processing . Brain and Language , 105 , 83 – 90 .

Saygin , A. P . ( 2007 ). Superior temporal and premotor brain areas necessary for biological motion perception . Brain , 130 , 2452 – 2461 .

Schuil , K. D. I. , Smits , M. , & Zwaan , R. A . ( 2013 ). Sentential context modulates the involvement of the motor cortex in action language processing: an fMRI study . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7 , 100 .

Schurz , M. , Radua , J. , Aichhorn , M. , Richlan , F. , & Perner , J . ( 2014 ). Fractionating theory of mind: a meta-analysis of functional brain imaging studies . Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews , 42 , 9 – 34 .

Sehm , B. , Schnitzler , T. , Obleser , J. , Groba , A. , Ragert , P. , Villringer , A. , & Obrig , H . ( 2013 ). Facilitation of inferior frontal cortex by transcranial direct current stimulation induces perceptual learning of severely degraded speech . Journal of Neuroscience , 33 , 15868 – 15878 .

Serino , A. , De Filippo , L. , Casavecchia , C. , Coccia , M. , Shiff rar , M. , & Ladavas , E . ( 2010 ). Lesions to the motor system aff ect action perception . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 22 , 413 – 426 .

Shtyrov , Y. , Butorina , A. , Nikolaeva , A. , & Stroganova , T . ( 2014 ). Automatic ultrarapid activation and inhibition of cortical motor systems in spoken word comprehension . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , E1918 – E1923 .

Slobin , D. I . ( 2000 ). Verbalized events: a dynamic approach to linguistic relativity and determinism . In S. Niemeier & R. Dirven (Eds.), Evidence for linguistic relativity (pp. 107 – 138 ). Amsterdam : John Benjamins .

Slobin , D. I . ( 2006 ). What makes manner of motion salient? Explorations in linguistic typology, discourse, and cognition . In M. Hickmann & S. Robert (Eds.), Space in languages: linguistic systems and cognitive categories (pp. 59 – 82 ). Amsterdam : John Benjamins .

Smalle , E. H. M. , Rogers , J. , & Möttönen , R . (in press). Dissociating contributions of the motor cortex to speech perception and response bias by using transcranial magnetic stimulation . Cerebral Cortex.

Spunt , R. P. , & Lieberman , M. D . ( 2012 ). Dissociating modality-specifi c and supramodal systems for action understanding . Journal of Neuroscience , 32 , 3575 – 3583 .

Taylor , L. J. , & Zwaan , R. A . ( 2009 ). Action in cognition: the case of language . Language and Cognition , 1 , 45 – 58 .

Tidoni , E. , Borgomaneri , S. , di Pellegrino , G. , & Avenanti , A . ( 2013 ). Action simulation plays a critical role in deceptive action recognition . Journal of Neuroscience , 33 , 611 – 623 .

Tomasino , B. , & Rumiati , R. I . ( 2013 ). At the mercy of strategies: the role of motor representations in language understanding . Frontiers in Psychology , 4 , 27 .

Tranel , D. , Kemmerer , D. , Adolphs , R. , Damasio , H. , & Damasio , A . ( 2003 ). Neural correlates of conceptual knowledge for actions . Cognitive Neuropsychology , 20 , 409 – 432 .

Tranel , D. , Manzel , K. , Asp , E. , & Kemmerer , D . ( 2008 ). Naming static and dynamic actions: neuropsychological evidence . Journal of Physiology–Paris , 102 , 80 – 94 .

Ubaldi , S. , Barchiesi , G. , & Cattaneo , L . (in press). Bottom-up and top-down responses to action observation . Cerebral Cortex .

Urgesi , C. , Calvo-Merino , B. , Haggard , P. , & Aglioti , S. M . ( 2007 a). Transcranial magnetic stimulation reveals two cortical pathways for visual body processing . Journal of Neuroscience , 27 , 8023 – 8030 .

Urgesi , C. , Candidi , M. , & Avenanti , A . ( 2014 ). Neuroanatomical substrates of action perception and understanding: an anatomic likelihood estimation meta-analysis of lesion-symptom mapping studies in brain injured patients . Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 8 , 344 .

Urgesi , C. , Candidi , M. , Ionta , S. , & Aglioti , S. M . ( 2007 b). Representation of body identity and body actions in extrastriate body area and ventral premotor cortex . Nature Neuroscience , 10 , 30 – 31 .

van Kemenade , B. M. , Muggleton , N. , Walsh , V. , & Saygin , A. P . ( 2012 ). The eff ects of TMS over STS and premotor cortices on the perception of biological motion . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 24 , 896 – 904 .

david kemmerer

26

Van Overwalle , F . ( 2009 ). Social cognition and the brain: a meta-analysis . Human Brain Mapping , 30 , 829 – 858 .

Van Overwalle , F. , & Baetens , K . ( 2009 ). Understanding others’ actions and goals by mirror and mentalizing systems: a meta-analysis . NeuroImage , 48 , 564 – 584 .

Vingerhoets , G. , Honoré , P. , Vandekerckhove , E. , Nys , J. , Vandemaele , P. & Achten , E . ( 2010 ). Multifocal intraparietal activation during discrimination of action intention in observed tool grasping . Neuroscience , 169 , 1158 – 1167 .

Watson , C. E. , Cardillo , E. R. , Ianni , G. R. , & Chatterjee , A . ( 2013 ). Action concepts in the brain: an activation-likelihood estimation meta-analysis . Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 25 , 1191 – 1205 .

Wheaton , K. J. , Thompson , J. C. , Syngeniotis , A. , Abbott , D. F. , & Puce , A . ( 2004 ). Viewing the motion of human body parts activates diff erent regions of premotor, temporal, and parietal cortex . Neuroimage , 22 , 277 – 288 .

Willems , R. M. , & Casasanto , D . ( 2011 ). Flexibility in embodied language understanding . Frontiers in Psychology , 2 , 116 .

Willems , R. M. , & Francken , J. C . ( 2012 ). Embodied cognition: taking the next step . Frontiers in Psychology , 3 , 582 .

Willems , R. M. , Labruna , L. , D’Esposito , M. , Ivry , R. , & Casasanto , D . ( 2011 ). A functional role for the motor system in language understanding: evidence from theta burst TMS . Psychological Science , 22 , 849 – 854 .

Wilson , M. , & Knoblich , G . ( 2005 ). The case for motor involvement in perceiving conspecifi cs . Psychological Bulletin , 131 , 460 – 473 .

Zwaan , R . ( 2014 ). Embodiment and language comprehension: reframing the discussion . Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 18 , 229 – 234 .


Recommended